Understanding Opinions: Worldviews and Entrails
We all have to believe something or other, but we seem to believe everything we think. Curious that.
Note: This essay was prepared with the research assistance and ghostwriting capabilities of ChatGPT 4.0 (sometimes good, sometimes quite horrible).
Author’s Preface:
I have read a lot of material over the last few days in the aftermath of the election in the United States. Now, I don't have a vested interest in that, being a Canadian—not in the same way that a U.S. citizen would—but I certainly have a vested interest in seeing world peace, harmony, and civil liberties restored, as well as freedom of speech in my own country. And I can't isolate my country from the rest of the world.
So, while I don't have "Trump Derangement Syndrome," I am not entirely convinced he’ll fulfill his promises. He has made a number of points I strongly agree with, and he has appointed some people with whom I mostly align. However, after reading follow-up articles from people in my alternative media community—some on the left, some U.S. Republicans—I see a huge range of opinion about Trump: his motivations, his future actions, and what he truly represents.
Some think it will be the same old story because they believe he is captured by the military-industrial complex and is at heart a warmonger, while others view him as a kind of savior, perhaps even a "second coming." I don’t know where the truth lies, and once again, this brings me back to a point I often make: so much of what we consider "fact" is really just opinion. In this essay, I use the metaphor of "reading the entrails" to explore this idea.
Introduction
In exploring the nature of belief, truth, and social understanding, we confront the complex interplay between objective facts, subjective interpretations, and culturally constructed conventions. While certain facts serve as essential foundations for survival and practical decision-making, much of what we consider knowledge falls within the domain of interpretation, colored by individual perspectives and worldviews. This distinction grows particularly sharp when we examine social conventions—shared understandings that vary widely across cultures and lack the fixedness of factual truths. Yet, individuals often cling to their interpretations as if they were universal truths, fostering disagreements and biases that are deeply embedded in human cognition. The following discussion examines these dynamics, questioning the lines between fact and interpretation and probing the limitations of objectivity in the realms of belief, social norms, and knowledge.
Discussion
Worldviews and Entrails
The metaphor of “reading the entrails” aptly describes how diverse groups—political pundits, armchair philosophers, everyday individuals, as well as academics and researchers—approach complex issues (cf. Nietzsche, 1887). Nietzsche's well-known claim that "there are no facts, only interpretations" seems mostly accurate, though it may oversimplify certain realities (Nietzsche, 1887/1974). While many facets of knowledge are interpretive, some information, particularly regarding practical matters like construction, safety, and technology, are factual and self-evident. Such facts transcend interpretation because they are based on verifiable and reproducible outcomes. However, when it comes to topics like political commentary, climate science, public opinion polling, medical science, and health research, these analyses become more speculative. Here, interpretation takes precedence, and we find ourselves once again reading the entrails to understand meaning (cf. Kahneman, 2011; Collins, 2002).
Divination and Human Limitations
Another way to describe this process of interpretation could be “reading tea leaves” or engaging in some form of divination, though humanity lacks notable skill in this area. Perhaps this limitation stems from insufficient intelligence or from the way we are conditioned by a mix of valid information, misinformation, and disinformation, without any consistently reliable method for distinguishing among them (cf. Aikin & Talisse, 2020). In some instances, we may succeed in teasing apart truth from falsehood, but this is not guaranteed. Personally, I approach this interpretive challenge from the perspective of a Pyrrhonian skeptic, a position that, rather than being merely pragmatic, reflects a core aspect of Pyrrhonian skepticism (Annas & Barnes, 1985). I suspect that Pyrrhonian skeptics of the past were practical in their everyday affairs while still holding a theoretical commitment to suspension of judgment. Like myself, they likely accepted many things without active questioning in their daily interactions.
Worldviews and Skepticism
Every individual holds a worldview, including skeptics who, like anyone else, determine some things to be true and others false, acting based on these judgments. This perspective may be adjusted over time due to new information, shifts in memory, or other factors (cf. Rorty, 1989). This process seems aligned with classical skeptical thought, which suggests that beliefs are provisional and subject to change based on new evidence or reflection. However, my knowledge of skepticism is limited to occasional readings and does not encompass formal scholarship in the area.
Competing Claims and Contradictions
A fundamental issue arises with competing claims that are so mutually exclusive they cannot be reconciled by any amount of nuance or qualification. In these cases, the claims stand in direct opposition, where basic logic dictates that both cannot be correct simultaneously (Aristotle, Metaphysics, Book IV). When applied to numerous contradictory claims, the situation only intensifies: at most, only one claim can be accurate among those that are entirely incompatible with each other. This illustrates the principle of non-contradiction, which states that contradictory propositions cannot both be true in the same context.
Correctness and Coincidence
In cases of competing claims, one claim might indeed be correct, but its correctness may be coincidental rather than reasoned. Typically, claims are not standalone; they are embedded within complex arguments, often challenging to analyze and requiring considerable effort to disentangle (cf. Toulmin, 1958). Even sophisticated tools, like ChatGPT, can struggle with this task, sometimes providing accurate summaries but frequently missing key points or introducing errors. Thus, among contradictory claims, one might be coincidentally correct or supported by argument. However, from a skeptical perspective, distinguishing between coincidental correctness and reasoned correctness is a tenuous endeavor at best, given the inherent uncertainties in interpretive processes (cf. Popper, 1959).
Proof and Psychological Conviction
Proof, in practice, operates more as an expression of belief than as a purely logical construct. While logic provides a structure for proofs, the validity of proof ultimately relies on psychological conviction. Without this conviction, one does not accept something as proven, despite any formal logical demonstration (cf. Wittgenstein, 1953). This is particularly relevant in communicative contexts, where proof must persuade others of its validity. Even in mathematics, where proofs are rigorously logical, acceptance of proof still depends on the mathematician's personal assurance of correctness, highlighting that proof is, fundamentally, a psychological process (cf. Lakatos, 1976).
Competing Claims and Interpretation
Returning to the issue of competing claims, only one claim, at most, can be correct for any given assertion, though it is often the case that a blend of true and false assertions coexist within complex arguments. This leaves us to interpret the claims much as one would “read the entrails” in divination—whether one is an accurate interpreter or simply coincidentally correct is not easily determined (cf. Collins, 2002). When observing pundits or commentators, it becomes clear that their assertions cannot all be simultaneously true, despite each claiming logic, evidence, and truth on their side. Yet, the evidence they present is inevitably subject to interpretation, with only the simplest cases yielding clarity without extensive interpretive effort (cf. Hanson, 1958). Ultimately, all analysis is a form of "reading the entrails," as interpretation remains embedded in every level of these evaluations.
Worldview and Its Inescapability
The concept of worldview is both universal and inescapable. Every person, regardless of background or perspective, possesses a worldview shaped by beliefs, biases, comprehension, and both linguistic and pre-linguistic understandings. This worldview encompasses our sensory experiences, encompassing both internal and external perceptions, as well as the various senses through which we interpret reality (cf. Dilthey, 1910). Additionally, worldview is influenced by an array of factors, some of which may appear arbitrary or random. Over time, our worldview adapts and shifts, though we inevitably adopt beliefs and values we deem accurate or reliable. This holds true for everyone—whether skeptic, cynic, optimist, or someone without a particular philosophical alignment. While committed skeptics may strive to hold their beliefs more tentatively, they, too, are bound by a worldview and are subject to the same limitations as others. In essence, holding a worldview is a necessity; it is not something one can opt out of (cf. Gadamer, 1960).
Divergence and Changing Perspectives
Throughout life, one often experiences shifts in alignment with others' views, routinely finding agreement with some people and disagreement with others. At times, a pundit, author, or speaker may initially seem insightful, yet over time, as one delves deeper into their ideas, areas of divergence begin to emerge. These differences may gradually reveal substantial or even fundamental shifts in values, leading to stark contrasts between one’s beliefs and those of the other person (cf. Rokeach, 1973). This process is common and can lead to significant changes in relationships: friendships may falter when fundamental disagreements arise, or admiration for public figures may wane once their core beliefs are understood and found incompatible with one’s own (cf. Festinger, 1957).
Worldview and External Interpretation
Worldview constitutes one part of the interpretive process by which we evaluate information—our metaphorical "reading of the entrails." The other part involves the external information we receive from others. Our interpretation of this information is influenced by multiple factors, with worldview being a key component but not the only one. Additional elements, such as prior experiences, cognitive biases, and emotional states, also shape how we process and integrate new information into our understanding (cf. Kelly, 1955).
Situational Influence on Belief
Situational factors and attributes of the speaker play significant roles in shaping our openness to new ideas, influencing how receptive we are to others' perspectives. These contextual elements subtly affect our interpretive process. Yet, despite these influences, we continue engaging in what can be likened to "reading the entrails," as interpretation remains a subjective and speculative endeavor (cf. Goffman, 1959; Cialdini, 2001).
Confusing Worldview with Truth
A major issue emerges when individuals mistake their personal worldview, or the perspectives presented by others, for objective truth. When information aligns with one's biases, it often goes unchallenged, even though both the individual and the information source might be entirely incorrect. Trust in these sources is shaped by various factors, including political biases, personal agendas, survival needs, corporate influence, and pressures toward conformity or groupthink. Despite these influences, the act remains akin to "reading the entrails," as interpretation is deeply subjective and shaped by external pressures (cf. Janis, 1982; Kahneman, 2011).
Consequences of Differing Beliefs
Disagreements over beliefs can lead to harmful outcomes when they escalate beyond mere differences of opinion. Friendships may dissolve, family bonds strain, and, on a broader scale, conflicts and wars are waged. These divisions can even lead to extreme actions such as torture, ostracism, and other detrimental consequences—all rooted in interpretive differences. As beliefs are subject to complex interpretive factors, this "reading of the entrails" reveals our attempts to make sense of things, though, collectively, we often struggle with accuracy and discernment (cf. Haidt, 2012; Festinger, 1957).
The Imperfections of Science
Science, too, is far from flawless; it faces significant, well-documented challenges. Contrary to the simplified, idealized version often taught to students, science is not a perfect, objective machine but is instead a complex and often imperfect process. Its portrayal as an infallible pathway to truth misses the nuanced reality, where biases, funding pressures, and human limitations frequently shape research outcomes (cf. Kuhn, 1962; Feyerabend, 1975).
Personal Skepticism and Belief
I do not claim to maintain a rigorously skeptical stance any more effectively than others. Like everyone, I establish certain foundational beliefs within my worldview. The primary difference may be that I approach both my own beliefs and the assertions of others with a somewhat heightened level of skepticism—though likely not enough. Despite this inclination, I still metaphorically "put a stake in the ground" for certain beliefs, some of which I hold quite firmly. My values, in particular, tend to be held with a degree of absolutism and are not readily subject to change (cf. Rokeach, 1973).
Change in Beliefs Over Time
A key point for any critical thinker is the recognition that beliefs held a decade ago likely differ from those held today. Beliefs evolve as we forget past views, encounter new information, and refine our understanding, often becoming more nuanced and qualified. Exposure to fresh ideas and the gradual fading of old ones contribute to this shift. While values tend to be more resistant to change than specific beliefs, they too can evolve over time as perspectives broaden or priorities shift (cf. Rokeach, 1973; Kuhn, 1962).
Values as a Species of Belief
Values can be understood as a subset of beliefs, distinguished primarily by their emotional significance. The term "values" reflects this resonance, suggesting that they may relate more closely to perceptions of what is appropriate or desirable rather than to objective truths. However, this distinction is not universal. Some individuals equate their values with truth, perceiving them as inherently correct rather than as subjective preferences (cf. Rokeach, 1973; Haidt, 2012).
Religion and Values
Religious adherents frequently perceive their beliefs as absolute truths, often viewing them as direct revelations from a divine source. From an agnostic or skeptical viewpoint, this conviction may seem unfounded, yet it is widely held, likely representing a majority perspective. Despite the diversity across religious and belief systems, people tend to form strong attachments to their religious views, integrating values that reinforce these beliefs. Often, these values, deeply entwined with religious identity, include positions that might now be regarded as outdated or even immoral by contemporary ethical standards (cf. Durkheim, 1912; Taylor, 2007).
Political Opinions and Media Influence
Political opinions are pervasive yet often problematic, as many people trust pundits despite these figures interpreting information in much the same speculative way as anyone else. Predictive fields, broadly speaking, tend to have poor accuracy, with polling in particular facing significant, well-documented issues (cf. Silver, 2016). Mainstream media similarly suffers from substantial, well-known problems, often functioning as paid advocates for wealthy and influential interests. Numerous journalists, including but not limited to Noam Chomsky, have highlighted issues of media bias and control, particularly regarding the influence exerted by governments and powerful entities. Consequently, trust in mainstream media may be misplaced (cf. Herman & Chomsky, 1988; McChesney, 2004).
Alternative Media and Subjective Interpretations
The short answer to whether alternative media is trustworthy is also no. Individuals in alternative media, regardless of sincerity, interpret information through their own worldview, ultimately engaging in the same speculative process as mainstream commentators. This interpretive approach means they may present perspectives that align with one’s own beliefs or appear correct, but this alignment offers no indication of actual accuracy. As with all competing opinions, when interpretations differ, at most one can be correct—if indeed any of them are correct at all (cf. McChesney, 2013; Pariser, 2011).
Worldview and Epistemic Bias
No one’s views deserve a privileged status in the realm of knowledge; they are no more likely to be true than anyone else’s. While personal beliefs may turn out to be accurate, they could just as easily be incorrect. Lacking the perspective of an omniscient being, one's views remain subjective interpretations rather than definitive truths (cf. Nagel, 1986). Yet, it is common for individuals to perceive their worldview from an assumed epistemic high ground, implicitly trusting their own thoughts and judgments as correct. This sense of epistemic privilege can obscure the possibility of error, reinforcing the potential for self-deception (cf. Kahneman, 2011).
Confirmation Bias and Attributing Negative Value
People often hold a deep-seated belief in their own correctness, viewing themselves as better informed, more rational, and ultimately "right," while attributing opposing views to others as stemming from poor information, propaganda, or sheer error. This mindset can lead not only to viewing others as simply mistaken but as fundamentally lacking in intelligence or even as morally deficient. Such assumptions are often unfounded and reveal an overreliance on one’s own perspective as privileged or inherently correct. This tendency, often fueled by confirmation bias, underscores the irrationality of dismissing differing perspectives as inferior rather than recognizing them as alternative interpretations of the same reality (cf. Nickerson, 1998; Haidt, 2012).
The Endemic Nature of Self-Righteousness
This tendency defies common sense, yet it persists widely. Like most people, I often believe my views are superior, considering myself more informed, a clearer thinker, with better access to reliable information. Simultaneously, others view me through the same lens, convinced that I am the one who is mistaken. This self-assurance appears endemic to human nature. Although I try to remember the pitfalls of assuming my beliefs are always correct, this self-reminder does not always prevent me from falling into the trap of self-righteousness (cf. Tversky & Kahneman, 1974; Pronin, Gilovich, & Ross, 2004).
Contradictory Assertions and Truth
Returning to the central issue, when two assertions are entirely contradictory, it is logically impossible for both to be true; however, this does not imply that either must be correct. In complex discussions, multiple contradictory assertions are often interwoven with points of agreement, further complicating the search for truth. Rarely do we limit ourselves to a single assertion, as multiple, interconnected points are typically presented, creating an intricate web of statements that can be challenging to untangle (cf. Aristotle, Metaphysics, Book IV; Toulmin, 1958).
Staking Territory on Truth
Despite logical complexities, we often cling to the conviction that our beliefs represent what is right and good, while opposing views are seen as misguided or even morally suspect. This tendency to "stake out territory" on what we consider truth is nearly universal, with each individual placing markers around beliefs they hold as accurate. The degree of attachment varies, with some individuals adopting a more dogmatic stance than others, but the impulse to claim truth as one’s own remains pervasive (cf. Festinger, 1957; Haidt, 2012).
Nietzsche on Facts and Interpretations
Nietzsche is often quoted, in translation, as saying, “There are no facts, only interpretations.” This perspective reflects his skepticism about objective truths, particularly in complex, abstract domains. While there is validity to his point—many of our beliefs are indeed shaped by interpretation—it may be an overstatement to say there are no facts at all. Practical, concrete facts are essential to navigate the world effectively, providing a basis for survival. Yet, once we move into complex or abstract issues, opinion increasingly overshadows factual certainty, suggesting that, while Nietzsche highlighted an important dynamic, he perhaps underestimated the role of factual knowledge in everyday life (cf. Nietzsche, 1887; Goodman, 1978).
Conventions and Social Understanding
Shared social understandings are better categorized as arbitrary conventions rather than facts. Such conventions lack the universality typically associated with factual information, as they are fluid and vary across individuals, communities, and cultures. These are not fixed truths but rather agreed-upon norms that facilitate social interaction within specific contexts. The variability of these conventions underscores their nature as culturally contingent rather than objectively factual (cf. Wittgenstein, 1953; Berger & Luckmann, 1966).
Summary
This exploration delves into the boundaries between objective facts, subjective interpretations, and culturally shaped conventions, highlighting the complex dynamics that inform human understanding and belief. While practical facts provide a foundation for survival and interaction with the physical world, interpretations dominate our perceptions, especially in complex or abstract domains. Social conventions, though not factual, serve as flexible frameworks that vary by culture and facilitate communal understanding. Yet, individuals frequently regard their interpretations as universal truths, leading to biases and conflicts that are ingrained in human thought. By examining these distinctions, the discussion underscores the challenges inherent in separating fact from belief, especially within the fluid realms of social norms and personal worldview.
References
Aikin, S. F., & Talisse, R. B. (2020). Pragmatism, pluralism, and the nature of philosophy. Routledge.
Aikin and Talisse are philosophers specializing in pragmatism and democratic theory. This work argues for a pluralistic approach to philosophy that accommodates diverse perspectives.
Annas, J., & Barnes, J. (1985). The modes of skepticism: Ancient texts and modern interpretations. Cambridge University Press.
Annas and Barnes are classicists and philosophers focused on ancient Greek philosophy. This book examines ancient skeptical texts, contrasting classical skepticism with contemporary interpretations.
Aristotle. (1984). Metaphysics (H. Tredennick, Trans.). Harvard University Press.
Aristotle, an ancient Greek philosopher, explores the foundations of being and reality. This work introduces key metaphysical principles like the law of non-contradiction.
Berger, P. L., & Luckmann, T. (1966). The social construction of reality: A treatise in the sociology of knowledge. Anchor Books.
Berger and Luckmann are sociologists known for their work on the sociology of knowledge. This text presents the idea that reality is socially constructed through shared beliefs and institutions.
Cialdini, R. B. (2001). Influence: Science and practice (4th ed.). Allyn & Bacon.
Cialdini, a social psychologist, is an expert on persuasion. This book identifies six principles of influence and explores the psychology of compliance.
Collins, H. M. (2002). Changing order: Replication and induction in scientific practice. Harvard University Press.
Collins is a sociologist specializing in scientific knowledge. This book analyzes the social processes involved in scientific replication and validation.
Dilthey, W. (1910). The essence of philosophy. University of North Carolina Press.
Dilthey, a German philosopher, emphasized the role of human experience in understanding. This work explores philosophy as a means of interpreting human life and reality.
Durkheim, É. (1912). The elementary forms of the religious life (J. W. Swain, Trans.). Free Press.
Durkheim, a sociologist, studied the social functions of religion. This work investigates how religion unites communities and shapes social norms.
Festinger, L. (1957). A theory of cognitive dissonance. Stanford University Press.
Festinger, a social psychologist, introduced cognitive dissonance theory, describing the discomfort of conflicting beliefs. This foundational work explains how people seek consistency in their beliefs.
Feyerabend, P. (1975). Against method. New Left Books.
Feyerabend, a philosopher of science, critiques rigid scientific methodologies. His work argues for methodological pluralism, claiming strict adherence to methods stifles discovery.
Gadamer, H.-G. (1960). Truth and method. Sheed & Ward.
Gadamer was a German philosopher known for his work in hermeneutics. This text explores understanding and interpretation, emphasizing tradition’s role in shaping truth.
Goffman, E. (1959). The presentation of self in everyday life. Doubleday Anchor.
Goffman, a sociologist, studied social interaction as performance. This work introduces the concept of individuals managing impressions to navigate social situations.
Goodman, N. (1978). Ways of worldmaking. Hackett Publishing Company.
Goodman, a philosopher, explored the concept of constructed realities. This work examines how science, art, and perception contribute to creating multiple “worlds.”
Haidt, J. (2012). The righteous mind: Why good people are divided by politics and religion. Pantheon Books.
Haidt is a social psychologist specializing in moral psychology. This book explains moral divisions across political and religious lines through evolutionary and cultural factors.
Hanson, N. R. (1958). Patterns of discovery: An inquiry into the conceptual foundations of science. Cambridge University Press.
Hanson, a philosopher of science, argued that observation is theory-laden. This work discusses how scientific discoveries are shaped by prior beliefs and frameworks.
Herman, E. S., & Chomsky, N. (1988). Manufacturing consent: The political economy of the mass media. Pantheon Books.
Herman and Chomsky examine media’s role in shaping public opinion. This work proposes a “propaganda model” where media serves elite interests.
Janis, I. L. (1982). Groupthink: Psychological studies of policy decisions and fiascoes (2nd ed.). Houghton Mifflin.
Janis was a social psychologist known for his research on groupthink. This book discusses how group pressures can lead to flawed decision-making.
Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. Farrar, Straus and Giroux.
Kahneman, a Nobel laureate, is known for his work on cognitive biases. This work contrasts intuitive and deliberate thinking modes, examining their roles in judgment.
Kelly, G. A. (1955). The psychology of personal constructs. Norton.
Kelly was a psychologist who developed personal construct theory. His work explores how individuals interpret experiences through unique conceptual frameworks.
Kuhn, T. S. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions. University of Chicago Press.
Kuhn, a historian of science, introduced the concept of paradigm shifts. This work argues that scientific progress occurs through revolutions rather than incremental change.
Lakatos, I. (1976). Proofs and refutations: The logic of mathematical discovery. Cambridge University Press.
Lakatos was a philosopher of mathematics known for his fallibilist approach. This work discusses mathematical discovery as a process of conjecture and refutation.
McChesney, R. W. (2004). The problem of the media: U.S. communication politics in the 21st century. Monthly Review Press.
McChesney is a media scholar focused on the impact of media ownership. This book critiques U.S. media for prioritizing commercial over public interests.
McChesney, R. W. (2013). Digital disconnect: How capitalism is turning the internet against democracy. The New Press.
McChesney examines how corporate control affects digital media. This book argues that profit motives undermine democratic access to information.
Nagel, T. (1986). The view from nowhere. Oxford University Press.
Nagel, a philosopher, explores objectivity and subjectivity. This work discusses the limits of objective understanding from a subjective standpoint.
Nickerson, R. S. (1998). Confirmation bias: A ubiquitous phenomenon in many guises. Review of General Psychology, 2(2), 175–220.
Nickerson, a psychologist, reviews confirmation bias, which affects reasoning and belief. His article discusses how individuals favor information that confirms pre-existing beliefs.
Nietzsche, F. (1887/1974). On the genealogy of morals (W. Kaufmann, Trans.). Random House.
Nietzsche, a philosopher, critiques the origins of moral values. This work explores how traditional morality is shaped by power dynamics and historical contingencies.
Pariser, E. (2011). The filter bubble: How the new personalized web is changing what we read and how we think. Penguin Books.
Pariser, an internet activist, critiques algorithm-driven content. His book discusses how personalization narrows exposure to diverse perspectives online.
Popper, K. R. (1959). The logic of scientific discovery. Hutchinson.
Popper, a philosopher of science, developed the criterion of falsifiability. His work argues that science advances by disproving hypotheses rather than confirming them.
Pronin, E., Gilovich, T., & Ross, L. (2004). Objectivity in the eye of the beholder: Divergent perceptions of bias in self versus others. Psychological Review, 111(3), 781–799.
This study by psychologists Pronin, Gilovich, and Ross examines bias in self vs. others. Their work explores the tendency to see oneself as less biased than others.
Rokeach, M. (1973). The nature of human values. Free Press.
Rokeach, a social psychologist, studies human values and their role in behavior. His work categorizes values and examines their influence on social attitudes.
Rorty, R. (1989). Contingency, irony, and solidarity. Cambridge University Press.
Rorty, a philosopher, explores the role of contingency in knowledge. His work advocates for a pragmatic approach to truth and solidarity beyond objective certainty.
Silver, N. (2016). The signal and the noise: Why so many predictions fail—but some don’t. Penguin Books.
Silver, a statistician, analyzes prediction failures across fields. His book emphasizes distinguishing meaningful data from noise in forecasting.
Taylor, C. (2007). A secular age. Belknap Press.
Taylor, a philosopher, examines the shift from religious to secular societies. His work traces the historical development and implications of secularization.
Toulmin, S. (1958). The uses of argument. Cambridge University Press.
Toulmin, a philosopher, presents a model of argumentation emphasizing practical reasoning. His work contrasts formal logic with everyday argument structures.
Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1974). Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Science, 185(4157), 1124–1131.
Tversky and Kahneman, cognitive psychologists, studied heuristics and cognitive biases. This seminal article reveals how biases shape judgments under uncertainty.
Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations (G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). Blackwell.
Wittgenstein, a philosopher, explores language and meaning. His work argues that language games and context shape understanding and communication.